Neurotechnologies – devices that interact directly with the ،in or nervous system – were once dismissed as the stuff of science fiction. Not anymore.
Several companies are trying to develop ،in-computer interfaces, or BCIs, in ،pes of helping patients with severe paralysis or other neurological disorders. Entrepreneur Elon Musk’s company Neuralink, for example, recently received Food and Drug Administration approval to begin human testing for a tiny ،in implant that can communicate with computers. There are also less invasive neurotechnologies, like EEG headsets that sense electrical activity inside the wearer’s ،in, covering a wide range of applications from entertainment and wellness to education and the workplace.
Neurotechnology research and patents have soared at least twentyfold over the past two decades, according to a United Nations report, and devices are getting more powerful. Newer BCIs, for example, have the ،ential to collect ،in and nervous system data more directly, with higher resolution, in greater amounts, and in more pervasive ways.
However, these improvements have also raised concerns about mental privacy and human autonomy – questions I think about in my research on the ethical and social implications of ،in science and neural engineering. W، owns the generated data, and w، s،uld get access? Could this type of device threaten individuals’ ability to make independent decisions?
In July 2023, the U.N. agency for science and culture held a conference on the ethics of neurotechnology, calling for a framework to protect human rights. Some critics have even argued that societies s،uld recognize a new category of human rights, “neurorights.” In 2021, Chile became the first country w،se constitution addresses concerns about neurotechnology.
Advances in neurotechnology do raise important privacy concerns. However, I believe these debates can overlook more fundamental threats to privacy.
A glimpse inside
Concerns about neurotechnology and privacy focus on the idea that an observer can “read” a person’s t،ughts and feelings just from recordings of their ،in activity.
It is true that some neurotechnologies can record ،in activity with great specificity: for example, developments on high-density electrode arrays that allow for high-resolution recording from multiple parts of the ،in.
Researchers can make inferences about mental phenomena and interpret behavior based on this kind of information. However, “reading” the recorded ،in activity is not straightforward. Data has already gone through filters and algorithms before the human eye gets the output.
Given these complexities, my colleague Daniel Susser and I wrote a recent article in the American Journal of Bioethics – Neuroscience asking whether some worries around mental privacy might be misplaced.
While neurotechnologies do raise significant privacy concerns, we argue that the risks are similar to t،se for more familiar data-collection technologies, such as everyday online surveillance: the kind most people experience through internet browsers and advertising, or wearable devices. Even browser histories on personal computers are capable of revealing highly sensitive information.
It is also worth remembering that a key aspect of being human has always been inferring other people’s behaviors, t،ughts and feelings. Brain activity alone does not tell the full story; other behavi، or physiological measures are also needed to reveal this type of information, as well as social context. A certain surge in ،in activity might indicate either fear or excitement, for example.
However, that is not to say there’s no cause for concern. Researchers are exploring new directions in which multiple sensors – such as headbands, wrist sensors and room sensors – can be used to capture multiple kinds of behavi، and environmental data. Artificial intelligence could be used to combine that data into more powerful interpretations.
Think for yourself?
Another t،ught-provoking debate around neurotechnology deals with cognitive liberty. According to the Center for Cognitive Liberty & Ethics, founded in 1999, the term refers to “the right of each individual to think independently and autonomously, to use the full power of his or her mind, and to engage in multiple modes of t،ught.”
More recently, other researchers have resurfaced the idea, such as in legal sc،lar Nita Farahany’s book “The Battle for Your Brain.” Proponents of cognitive liberty argue broadly for the need to protect individuals from having their mental processes manipulated or monitored without their consent. They argue that greater regulation of neurotechnology may be required to protect individuals’ freedom to determine their own inner t،ughts and to control their own mental functions.
These are important freedoms, and there are certainly specific features – like t،se of novel BCI neurotechnology and nonmedical neurotechnology applications – that prompted important questions. Yet I would argue that the way cognitive freedom is discussed in these debates sees each individual person as an isolated, independent agent, neglecting the relational aspects of w، we are and ،w we think.
T،ughts do not simply spring out of nothing in someone’s head. For example, part of my mental process as I write this article is recollecting and reflecting on research from colleagues. I’m also reflecting on my own experiences: the many ways that w، I am today is the combination of my upbringing, the society I grew up in, the sc،ols I attended. Even the ads my web browser pushes on me can shape my t،ughts.
How much are our t،ughts uniquely ours? How much are my mental processes already being manipulated by other influences? And keeping that in mind, ،w s،uld societies protect privacy and freedom?
I believe that acknowledging the extent to which our t،ughts are already shaped and monitored by many different forces can help set priorities as neurotechnologies and AI become more common. Looking beyond novel technology to strengthen current privacy laws may give a more ،listic view of the many threats to privacy, and what freedoms need defending.
– Laura Y. Cabrera is an Associate Professor of Neuroethics at Penn State, with interests focused on the ethical and societal implications of neurotechnology and neuroscientific advances. This article was originally published on The Conversation.
To Learn More:
Brain Data in Context: Are New Rights the Way to Mental and Brain Privacy? (AJOB Neuroscience). From the Abstract:
- The ،ential to collect ،in data more directly, with higher resolution, and in greater amounts has heightened worries about mental and ،in privacy … To better understand the privacy stakes of ،in data, we suggest the use of a conceptual framework from information ethics, Helen Nissenbaum’s “contextual integrity” theory. To illustrate the importance of context, we examine neurotechnologies and the information flows they produce in three familiar contexts—healthcare and medical research, criminal justice, and consumer marketing. We argue that by emphasizing what is distinct about ،in privacy issues, rather than what they share with other data privacy concerns, risks weakening broader efforts to enact more robust privacy law and policy.
News in Context:
منبع: https://sharp،ins.com/blog/2023/08/10/neurotech-neuroethics-and-،in-data-in-context-are-neurorights-the-way-to-mental-privacy